Immanuel Kant
Home ] Up ] Personal Identity ] Mind and Body ] Epistemology ] Readings ]

 

Religious Ethics
John Stuart Mill
Immanuel Kant
Aristotle
Carol Gilligan
Group Project #4


(BIOGRAPHY: Immanuel Kant was one of the greatest figures in the history of metaphysics. After 1755 he taught at the Univ. of Konigsberg and achieved wide renown through his teachings and writings. According to Kant, his reading of David Hume woke him from his dogmatic slumber and led him to become the "critical philosopher," synthesizing the rationalism of Leibniz and the skepticism of Hume. Kant proposed that objective reality is known only insofar as it conforms to the essential structure of the knowing mind. Only objects of experience, phenomena, may be known, whereas things lying beyond experience, noumena, are unknowable, even though in some cases we assume a priori knowledge of them. The existence of such unknowable "things-in-themselves" can be neither confirmed nor denied, nor can they be scientifically demonstrated. Therefore, as Kant showed in the Critique of Pure Reason (1781), the great problems of metaphysics -- the existence of God, freedom, and immortality -- are insoluble by scientific thought. Yet he went on to state in the Critique of Practical Reason (1788) that morality requires belief in their existence. Kant's Ethics centers in his categorical imperative, or absolute moral law, "Act as if the maxim from which you act were to become through your will a universal law." His Critique of Judgment (1790) considered the concepts of beauty and purposiveness as a bridge between the sensible and the intelligible worlds. Kant's influence on modern philosophy has continued to the present day. His work fostered the development of German idealism by Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. The Neo-Kantianism of the late 19th cent. applied his insights to the study of the physical sciences (Hermann Cohen, Ernst Cassirer), and to the historical and cultural sciences (Heinrich Rickert); his influence is also seen in the thought of Dilthey; in the pragmatism of John Dewey and William James; in the theology of Schleiermacher; and in gestalt psychology.)

There's no way around it -- Kant is rough going. Here a list of terms you will encounter, to help you unpack some difficult (but ultimately very insightful) text.

Will: that part of a person that reasons about and decides what to do (sometimes equated with practical reason). Because of the tie-in with reason, the activity of willing is constrained by the laws of logic. Hence if it is impossible for two things to both be true, one cannot will both. (You can at most wish for both).

Duty: One's duty is what one morally ought to do. For Kant, it is not enough for one to simply act as duty demands, but (AND THIS IS CRITICAL) that one's motivation for doing one's duty is just because it is one's duty. (You do it because it's what you ought to do, and not because it's in your interest, or it promotes the general happiness, etc.) All rational creatures have the same moral duty -- to act as the categorical imperative instructs. (See CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE).

Principle of the Will: the principle upon which one acts in a given situation. (Equivalent expression: PRINCIPLE OF VOLITION).

Maxim: A general statement of the principle upon which one acts in a given situation. If I lie to my friend to avoid harm to myself, then the principle of my will or volition would be "It is permissible to lie to one's friends if by lying one avoids harm to oneself." (Also called the subjective principle of one's action).

Acting according to the conception of laws: Humans (unlike non-rational creatures) can formulate a principle for themselves (i.e. "Never eat anything bigger than your head") and then act according to that principle (i.e. by never eating anything bigger than one's head). Non-rational creatures can only act as instinct demands. This is a critical difference for Kant, for it forms the very basis of our ability to act morally at all.

Acting out of respect for the law: "Law" here does not refer to the statutes and codes of the written law, but the moral law. To act out of respect for the law is to do what one ought to do (to DO ONE'S DUTY) because one recognizes that it is what one ought to do.

Actions which are recognized as objectively necessary are subjectively contingent: an action is objectively necessary if it is required by duty, but subjectively contingent because whether or not we human beings do it depends upon our imperfectly rational wills. So an objectively necessary action is objective in that it comes from reason (which is valid for all rational agents), and necessary insofar as reason commands it. Such actions are also subjectively contingent because they depend upon a particular rational agent (a subject) whose will may or may not impel her to act as reason dictates (hence everything is contingent upon her will).

Imperative: a statement or principle which states what one ought to do, (e.g. a command). Two types:

HYPOTHETICAL -- principle which requires one to do something only if he or she happens to desire a certain end. Example: "If you want to lose weight, then you should go on a diet."

CATEGORICAL -- principle which requires one to perform a certain action regardless of the ends one desires. Kant holds that there is only one categorical imperative, and it is the supreme principle of morality. Unfortunately, he gives us three formulations of that imperative, not all of which are equivalent. Here they are:

1) Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.

2) Act as it the maxim of thy action were to become by thy will a universal law of nature.

3) So act as to treat humanity, whether in thine own person or in that of any other, in every case as an end withal, and never as a means only.

OUTLINE OF THE SELECTION:

I. The Good Will

A.  The will (understood as that faculty by which a person reasons about and decides what to do) is the only thing that is good without qualification (i.e. is always and everywhere to be valued and esteemed).

1. Talents of the mind (intelligence,wit, etc.), character traits (courage, resolve, perseverance, etc), and gifts of fortune (wealth, power, etc) all are good or bad, depending upon the will that guides them.  

B. The value of a good will comes not from what it brings about, but is good merely for what it is -- the ability to choose rightly.

II. Everything acts according to laws

1. Animals act according to their natural instincts, what we call "laws of nature".

2. Humans can act either according to instinct, or according to principles they impose upon themselves.

a. If a person always did what reason told him to do ("reason infallibly determined his will"), then he would always do the right thing. Since humans don't always do what reason tells them, (our wills are also influenced by desires) they experience the commands of reason as constraints which we do not always follow.

b. "Command of reason" -- when an objective principle constrains the will; the statement of formulation of this command is an imperative.

II. The Main Types of Imperatives

A . Hypothetical imperatives are conditional commands; they command an action because that action is a means to something else the will desires.

Example: "If you want to lose weight, you ought to eat less."

1. Types of hypothetical imperatives:

a. Problematic: Imperative of skill; provides direction about how to go about achieving any particular end.

b. Assertorial: Imperative of prudence which seeks happiness. Example: "You desire happiness by necessity of nature; therefore you ought to perform these actions."

NOTE: The force of the "ought" in these imperatives is derived from the end they seek. Hence their value lies not in the action they prescribe, but in the end the act aims for. Kant wants moral imperatives to command unconditionally; their value is not dependent upon the results they achieve, but they are good in themselves.

B. Categorical Imperatives command one unconditionally. The goodness of such an action essentially depends on whether the agent's mental intention is to make his action comform to the principle that requires it.

The single basic principle of the CI is this:

Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law.

MAXIM: A general statement of the principle upon which one acts in a given situation. If I lie to my friend to get myself out of a jam, the principle of my volition (will) would be "It is permissible to lie to one's friends if by lying one avoids harm to oneself."

 

III. Examples of the CI in action:

A. Perfect duties are duties that it would be immoral not to do; imperfect duties are duties that would be meritorious to do, but not immoral not to do.

1. Another method of determining perfect from imperfect is to ask yourself two questions:

a) Can I conceive of a world in which everyone follows this principle? (If no, then we have a perfect duty, i.e. we cannot act upon the maxim in question. If yes, go to (b).)

b) Would I be willing to live in such a world? If no, then we have an imperfect duty not to act upon the maxim in question. If yes, then maxim harmonizes with CI, and hence commands categorically.

III. Rationality as an objective end

A. Objects of desire have conditional value.

1. They have value only if we possess the desire for them; no desire, no value.

a. Neither is the desire itself valuable, for all rational creatures would like to be free of them.

B. Rational beings have unconditional value.

1. Non-rational creatures are called things because they have only relative value. They may be used as means to an end.

2. Rational creatures are called persons because they are ends in themselves. They may not be used as simply as a means.

This is why the categorical imperative binds us unconditionally; unlike hypothetical imperatives, whose ends have value only if one values that end (conditional worth), categorical imperatives (which deal with persons) embody an end that has absolute or unconditional worth.